For Plato, the best art is didactic; it serves only to point
to an idea. In Plato’s mind, symbolic art is the only art worth allowing in a
republic. Hegel does not agree. In Hegel’s Aesthetics, symbolic art is
described as the lowest form of art. (Though we should note that he still
considers the symbolic art.)
According to Hegel, art must contain both concept and form;
each of these which must be concrete in itself. In a truly successful artwork
concept and form are perfectly melded. The symbolic meaning of the piece must
be reflected in the form of its representation. Thus, the Idea points to the
form and the form points back to the Idea. If concept and form are both viable
and well-executed, then the work becomes entirely self-contained producing a
message outside the viewer independent of the viewer’s individual perspective.
This self-containment is art’s bridge to universality. And only in being
entirely self-referential can art be timelessly and universally relevant.
Hegel describes the composition of symbols as: “(i) the
meaning, and (ii) the expression thereof” (304). This sounds identical to the
argument posed in his Aesthetics, where content and form combine to create an
Idea. So, I believe Hegel is saying that fine art is a symbol within itself.
Symbolic art, then seems to be something different. Symbolic art spears to be a
misuse or misunderstanding of the true nature of symbolism, in which form and
content are disjointed and largely unsuccessful in communicate a deeper Idea.
Hegel’s Aesthetics explains that symbolic art is not very
successful in the blending of concept and form. The form is often overly
simplistic and the ideas encompassed in the composition are too large to be
conveyed through the Egyptians’ simple style. Though they concept is much more
powerful than the form in symbolic art, it is the form that is notable. It is
immediately apparent in viewing the form of Egyptian art, that there is a large
and important concept behind everything they created. But the external obviousness
that there exists an grander idea has none of fine art’s required subtlety.
This means the simplicity of the form in comparison to the idea does not
highlight the idea, but rather, by too directly referencing its existence, emphasizes
form and obfuscates the idea. It is for this reason that Hegel declares
symbolic art, which is epitomized in Egyptian architecture, to be the least
successful of all the arts.
Hegel’s primary example of Egyptian symbolism is the
Pyramids because they “put before our eyes the simple prototype of symbolic art
itself” (356). The fascination the Pyramids ceaselessly engender is evidence of
the imbalance of concept and form in their construction. Had these two symbolic
elements been balanced, there would be no question of the meaning or purpose of
the Pyramids. However, “they are prodigious crystals which conceal in
themselves an inner meaning” (356). The Pyramids have frustrated and fascinated
generations because their enigmatic form clearly hints at a definite meaning
within their structure, yet their impressive form reveals little about what
that meaning might be. As Hegel says, “the shape for such an inner meaning
still remains just an external form and veil for the definite content of that
meaning” (356). The inharmonious blend of idea and form ensures that “inner
meaning rests concealed” (356). So, as fine art, Hegel would declare the
Pyramids unsuccessful.
Hegel goes on to compare Egyptian art to riddles: “we regard
the Egyptian works of art as containing riddles, the right solution of which is
in part unattained not only by us, but generally by those who posed these riddles
to themselves” (360). He clearly thinks that the failure of attaining true
symbolism within Egyptian art is due to an incomplete grasp of what the artists
were hoping to convey, meaning that their art cannot help us grasp at a more
concrete understanding of these concepts, merely suggest their existence. So, “Egyptian
symbols, as we saw at the very beginning, contain implicitly much, explicitly
nothing,” thus making them relatively unvalued in aesthetic terms (360).
From his brief talk of riddles, Hegel naturally progresses
to the Sphinx, a mythical creature famously associated with the Egyptians. Hegel
claims the sphinx “the symbol of the symbolic itself” (360). For this reason, I
would claim that the sphinx is a symbol in Hegel’s highest sense of the word.
Like fine art, the sphinx is both a formal and ideological representation of an
Idea, in this case, a riddle. Hegel’s original description of “the symbol is no
purely arbitrary sign, but a sign in which externality comprises in itself at
the same time the content of the idea which it brings into appearance” (305).
A riddle cannot be art, because the answer is evident only
externally. For example, the riddle the Sphinx gives Oedipus requires him to
look within himself for the answer. He must follow the command to “Know thyself”.
This is in accordance with Kant’s ideals of art, where the nature of art must
echo with something inside of us. It is completely contrary to Hegel’s
aesthetics for the same reason. For Hegel, all art must have a self-contained
meaning. Though the riddle does not represent this to Hegel, I would argue that
the sphinx does.
No comments:
Post a Comment